2.6.3. Making Estimates
2.6.3.1. Identifying Extreme Values, Ranges, and Thresholds
It is worth noting that by failing to provide an estimate of the full range
of outcomes (i.e., not specifying outliers that include rapid nonlinear events),
authors of previous assessments were not conveying to potential users a representation
of the full range of uncertainty associated with the estimate. This has important
implications with regard to the extent to which the report accurately conveyed
to policymakers potential benefits or risks that may exist, even if at a low
or unknown probability (see Figure 2-1). If it were
necessary to truncate the range, it should have been clearly explained what
the provided range includes and/or excludes. Furthermore, the authors might
have specified how likely it is that the answer could lie outside the truncated
distribution.
Pittock and Jones (1999) recommend construction of thresholds that can be linked
to projected ranges of climate change. Such thresholds can account for biophysical
and/or socioeconomic criteria in the initial stages of an assessment but must
be expressed in climatic terms (e.g., above a certain temperature, rainfall
frequency, water balance, or combination of several factors). Further analysis
compares these thresholds with projected regional climate change. Similar approaches
are contained in concepts of tolerable climate change (see Hulme and Brown,
1998).
2.6.3.2. Valuation Issues
Any comprehensive attempt to evaluate the societal value of climate change
should include, in addition to the usual monetary value of items or services
traded in markets, measures of valued items or services that are not easily
marketed. Schneider et al. (2000) refer to this costing problem in vulnerability
analysis as "The Five Numeraires": monetary loss, loss of human life,
reductions in quality of life (including forced migration, conflicts over environmentally
dependent resources, loss of cultural diversity, loss of cultural heritage sites,
etc.), loss of species/biodiversity, and increasing inequity in the distribution
of material well-being. There is little agreement on how to place a monetary
value on the nonmarket impacts of climate change, yet such valuation is essential
to several analytic techniques to assess the efficiency or cost-effectiveness
of alternative climate policy proposals (see Section 2.5.6).
One such technique for valuation is to survey expert opinion on subjective
assessment of probability distributions of climate damage estimates (see Nordhaus,
1994a; Morgan and Keith, 1995; Titus and Narayanan, 1996, for examples of decision
analytic elicitations of climate effects and impacts; see Morgan and Dowlatabadi,
1996, for examples of how such elicited subjective probability distributions
can be incorporated into IAMs that examine "optimal" policies). An
alternative valuation framework is to use "cultural theory" (Douglas
and Wildavsky, 1982) to identify different value perspectives in designing policy
strategies (see van Asselt and Rotmans, 1995, for an application to population
growth). With this technique, subjective judgment about uncertainties may be
described from the viewpoints of different cultural perspectives. Preferred
policy options depend on the perspective adopted. Real policy choice, of course,
depends on the logic and consistency of formulating a basis for policy choices
(i.e., the role of decision analysis tools) and on the values of decisionmakers
at all levels. More formal and explicit incorporation of uncertainties into
decision analysis is the emphasis here.
|