7.2.5 Discounting
The debate on discount rates is a long-standing one. As SAR notes (IPCC, 1996a,
Chapter 4), there are two approaches to discounting; an ethical, or prescriptive,
approach based on what rates of discount should be applied, and a descriptive
approach based on what rates of discount people (savers as well as investors)
actually apply in their day-to-day decisions. SAR notes that the former lead
to relatively low rates of discount (around 2%33% in real terms) and the
latter to relatively higher rates (at least 6% and, in some cases, very much
higher rates).
The ethical approach applies the so-called social rate of time discount, which
is the sum of the rate of pure time-preference and the rate of increase of welfare
derived from higher per capita incomes in the future. The descriptive approach
takes into consideration the market rate of return to investments, whereby conceptually
funds can be invested in projects that earn such returns, with the proceeds
being used to increase the consumption for future generations. Portney and Weyant
(1999) provide a good overview of the literature on the issue of intergenerational
equity and discounting.
For climate change the assessment of mitigation programmes and the analysis
of impacts caused by climate change need to be distinguished. The choice of
discount rates applied in cost assessment should depend on whether the perspective
taken is the social or private case. The issues involved in the application
of discount rates in this context are addressed below.
For mitigation effects, the country must base its decisions at least partly
on discount rates that reflect the opportunity cost of capital. In developed
countries rates around 4%6% are probably justified. Rates of this level
are in fact used for the appraisal of public sector projects in the European
Union (EU) (Watts, 1999). In developing countries the rate could be as high
as 10%12%. The international banks use these rates, for example, in appraising
investment projects in developing countries. It is more of a challenge, therefore,
to argue that climate change mitigation projects should face different rates,
unless the mitigation project is of very long duration. These rates do not reflect
private rates of return, which typically need to be considerably higher to justify
the project, potentially between 10% and 25%.
For climate change impacts, the long-term nature of the problem is the key
issue. The benefits of reduced GHG emissions vary with the time of emissions
reduction, with the atmospheric GHG concentration at the reduction time, and
with the total GHG concentrations more than 100 years after the emissions reduction.
These are very difficult to assess.
Any realistic discount rate used to discount the impacts of increased
climate change impacts would render the damages, which occur over long periods
of time, very small. With a horizon of around 200 years, a discount rate of
4% implies that damages of US$1 at the end the period are valued at 0.04 cents
today. At 8% the same damages are worth 0.00002 cents today. Hence, at discount
rates in this range the damages associated with climate change become very small
and even disappear (Cline, 1993).
A separate issue is that of the discount rate to be applied to carbon. In a
mitigation cost study, should reductions of GHG in the future be valued less
than reductions today? It could argued that this is the case, as the impacts
of future reductions will be less. This is especially true of sink
projects, some of which will yield carbon benefits well into the future. Most
estimates of the cost of reductions in GHGs do not, however apply a discount
rate to the carbon changes. Instead, they simply take the average amount of
carbon stored or reduced over the project lifetime (referred to as flow summation)
or take the amount of carbon stored or reduced per year (flow summation divided
by the number of years). Both these methods are inferior to the application
of a discount rate to allow for the greater benefit of present reductions over
future reductions. The actual value, however remains a matter of disagreement,
but the case for anything more than a very low rate is hard to make (Boscolo
et al., 1998).
More recent analysis on discounting now examines rates that vary with the time
period considered. In surveys of individual trade-offs over time, Cropper et al. (1994) estimated a nominal rate of around 16.8%, based on a sophisticated
questionnaire approach to valuing present versus future risks. Most importantly,
however, these authors found evidence that respondents do not discount future
lives saved at a constant exponential rate of discount. Rather, median rates
seem to be decline over time (i.e., a rate is not constant over time but decreases
as the time horizon lengthens). Using different econometric specifications that
allow the discount rate to decline over time, Cropper et al. (1994) estimate
that mean discount rates are greater for short time periods relative to long
time horizons. For example, fitting their data to a hyperbolic function suggests
that mean discount rate is 0.80 for 1 year and 0.08 for 100 years. While the
pattern is consistent, the implied rates using linear discount rate functions
are much larger: 34% for the initial period and about 12% for the last period.
Hyperbolic discounting implies that a persons relative evaluation of
two payments depends on both the delay between the two payments and when this
delay will occursooner or later. For instance, people often have an impulsive
preference for immediate reward. Some people prefer to receive US$1000 today
over US$1010 in a months time, and yet they also prefer US$1010 in 21
months to US$1000 in 20 months, even though both choices involve a months
wait to obtain $10 more (see Lowenstein and Prelec, 1992). Theoretical support
for hyperbolic discount rests on the idea that, while interest rates from financial
instruments can be used to identify appropriate discount rates for time horizons
of a few decades, they do not apply to future interest rates for far distant
horizons. These will be determined by future opportunity sets created by many
factors, such as economic growth. The fact that the scope of these future opportunity
sets for the far distant future is not known adds another layer of uncertainty
into climate policy, which tends to drive discount rates down.
Weitzman (1998) surveyed 1700 professional economists and found that (a) economists
believe that lower rates should be applied to problems with long time horizons,
such as that being discussed here, and (b) they distinguish between the immediate
and, step by step, the far distant future. The discount rate implied by the
analysis falls progressively, from 4% to 0%, as the perspective shifts from
the immediate (up to 5 years hence) to the far distant future (beyond 300 years).
Weitzman (1998) suggests the appropriate discount rate for long-lived projects
is less than 2%. Finally, hyperbolic discounting has less support if it leads
to time-inconsistent planning, as argued by Cropper and Laibson (1999). Time
inconsistency arises when a policymaker has an incentive to deviate from a plan
made with another person, say in the future, even when no new information has
emerged. Policymakers of today try to commit future policymakers to a development
path that is sustainable. But when the future actually arrives, these new policymakers
deviate from the sustainable path and reallocate resources that are efficiently
based on prevailing interest rates.
Finally the case is made for calculating all intertemporal effects with more
than one rate. The arguments outlined above for different rates are unlikely
to be resolved, given that they have been an issue since well before climate
change. Hence it is good practice to calculate the costs for more than one rate
to provide the policymaker with some guidance on how sensitive the results are
to the choice of discount rate.7
A lower rate based on the ethical considerations is, as noted above, around
3%.
|